samedi 28 septembre 2024

Comment un juge doit apprécier l’absence de preuve d’une raison de mentir d'un témoin ou de son absence d’amplification lorsqu'il rend témoignage

R. c. Gerrard, 2022 CSC 13

Lien vers la décision


[4]               Deux de ces facteurs appellent quelques commentaires additionnels. L’absence de preuve qu’un plaignant a des raisons de mentir peut être pertinente dans l’appréciation de la crédibilité, particulièrement lorsque la défense suggère qu’il en a (R. c. Stirling2008 CSC 10[2008] 1 R.C.S. 272, par. 10‑11R. c. Ignacio2021 ONCA 69400 C.C.C. (3d) 343, par. 38 et 52). L’absence de preuve d’une raison de mentir ou l’existence de preuve réfutant une raison particulière de mentir constitue un facteur empreint de bon sens qui tend à indiquer qu’un témoin pourrait être davantage susceptible de dire la vérité parce qu’il n’a pas de raison de mentir. Cela dit, lorsque le juge qui préside un procès prend ce facteur en considération, il doit avoir deux risques à l’esprit : (1) l’absence de preuve qu’un plaignant a des raisons de mentir (c.‑à‑d. l’absence de preuve dans un sens ou dans l’autre) ne peut être assimilée à une preuve réfutant l’existence d’une raison particulière de mentir (c.‑à‑d. une preuve établissant que la raison n’existe pas), car la seconde situation requiert qu’on en fasse la preuve et constitue donc une indication plus solide de crédibilité — aucune de ces situations n’est concluante dans l’analyse sur la crédibilité; et (2) on ne peut renverser le fardeau de la preuve en exigeant que l’accusé démontre que le plaignant a une raison de mentir ou qu’il explique pourquoi le plaignant a formulé des allégations (R. c. Swain2021 BCCA 207406 C.C.C. (3d) 39, par. 31‑33).

[5]               L’absence d’amplification peut elle aussi être pertinente dans l’appréciation de la crédibilité d’un plaignant et elle se soulève souvent par suite de suggestions portant que le plaignant a des raisons de mentir. Cependant, contrairement à l’absence de preuve d’une raison de mentir ou à l’existence de preuve réfutant une raison particulière de mentir, l’absence d’amplification n’est pas un indice qu’un témoin est davantage susceptible de dire la vérité, car tant une déposition véridique qu’une déposition malhonnête peut ne contenir aucune exagération ou amplification. L’absence d’amplification ne peut pas être invoquée pour renforcer la crédibilité du plaignant — elle a tout simplement pour effet de ne pas nuire à la crédibilité. Elle peut toutefois constituer un facteur à prendre en considération dans l’examen de la question de savoir si un témoin avait ou non une raison de mentir.

Qu'est-ce que la collusion involontaire?

R. v Richer, 2023 ONSC 3158

Lien vers la décision


[249]      Inadvertent tainting, also referred to as innocent collusion, occurs when a witness’ testimony is influenced by hearing evidence from other witnesses.  Through conversation with others, a witness may start to remember the situation in question differently or certain details differently or the witness may interpret differently what he or she heard or saw or felt, as a result of hearing the interpretations of others.  The inadvertent or innocent nature of this form of witness contamination refers to the fact that it can happen without the witness ever intending to seek out information with a view to changing or aligning their own account.  It can happen subconsciously, without the witness even being aware that his or her later account or interpretation of events has been subtly changed by hearing the views and accounts of others.  [8]

[250]      Inadvertent tainting should be distinguished from collusion which is the term used to describe the situation in which witnesses get together and decide together what they are going to say to the police and/or in court to appear to be telling a consistent and reliable story.[9]

[251]      It is important to note that just because one witness has heard what someone else will say or believes happened, or has discussed another person’s recollections or interpretations, it does not necessarily mean that either witness is not telling the truth or that their evidence was tainted.[10]

[252]      Outright collusion between witnesses is a credibility issue.  If a court finds that witnesses have actively tried to “get their stories straight,” the ability of the court to find that those witnesses are honest and credible and are intending to tell the truth is compromised.  Inadvertent tainting is a reliability issue.  A witness whose evidence has been tainted, without him or her realizing it, through inadvertent tainting, may well be a credible witness who appears to be honest, forthright and telling the truth.  The witness may well believe he or she is telling the truth.  But the fact that his or her account has changed, even subtly, but in a relevant way, because of discussions with others, means that it may be less reliable.[11]

[253]      As Justice Nordheimer wrote in R. v. C.G.[12]:

The key point is that, unlike [collusion] which corrupts the evidence of all participants, where [inadvertent tainting] has occurred, a close examination is required to determine what impact that innocent sharing of information may have had on the evidence of each of the witnesses who is a party to the exchange.  As Sopinka, J. said in R. v. Burke1996 CanLII 229 (SCC), [1996] 1 S.C.R. 474, at para. 45:

Under this approach, the trier of fact is obliged to consider the reliability of the evidence having regard to all the circumstances, including the opportunities for collusion or collaboration to concoct the evidence and the possibility that these opportunities were used for such a purpose. [Emphasis in original.]

Il n'y a aucune présomption de véracité envers le témoin lorsque celui-ci témoigne

R. v. Thain, 2009 ONCA 223

Lien vers la décision


3) Witnesses are not presumed to be truthful

[32]         Witnesses are not “presumed to tell the truth”.  The evidence of each witness is to be assessed in the light of the totality of the evidence without any presumptions except the general and over-riding presumption of innocence.  Perhaps a generous reading of the final sentence in the impugned passage could be that, as it was applied to the evidence of the accused, it somehow resurrected the presumption of innocence apparently ignored in the preceding sentence.  However, as we are dealing here with basic and fundamental rights essential to a fair trial, I do not think it appropriate to salvage what appears to me to be a clear error with a strained and generous reading of this final sentence.

Revue des principes légaux pertinents par la Cour d'appel de Nouvelle-Écosse face à un dossier en appel lorsque la question de la crédibilité est centrale

R. v. Stanton, 2021 NSCA 57

Lien vers la décision


[67]         Before embarking on an assessment of the trial judge’s reasons to determine whether he committed legal error, I set out below the legal principles relevant to appeals where credibility is pivotal:

        The focus in appellate review “must always be on whether there is reversible error in the trial judge’s credibility findings”. Error can be framed as “insufficiency of reasons, misapprehension of evidence, reversing the burden of proof, palpable and overriding error, or unreasonable verdict” (R. v. G.F.2021 SCC 20, para. 100).

 

        Where the Crown’s case is wholly dependent on the testimony of the complainant it is essential the credibility and reliability of the complainant’s evidence be tested in the context of all the rest of the evidence (R. v. R.W.B.[1993] B.C.J. No. 758, para. 28 (C.A.).

        Assessments of credibility are questions of fact requiring an appellate court to re-examine and to some extent reweigh and consider the effects of the evidence. An appellate court cannot interfere with an assessment of credibility unless it is established that it cannot be supported on any reasonable review of the evidence (R. v. Delmas2020 ABCA 152, para. 5; upheld 2020 SCC 39).

        “Credibility findings are the province of the trial judge and attract significant deference on appeal” (G.F., para. 99). Appellate intervention will be rare (R. v. Dinardo2008 SCC 24, para. 26).

        Credibility is a factual determination. A trial judge’s findings on credibility are entitled to deference unless palpable and overriding error can be shown (R. v. Gagnon2006 SCC 17, paras. 10-11).

 

        Once the complainant asserts that she did not consent to the sexual activity, the question becomes one of credibility. In assessing whether the complainant consented, a trial judge “must take into account the totality of the evidence, including any ambiguous or contradictory conduct by the complainant...” (R. v. Ewanchuk1999 CanLII 711 (SCC)[1999] 1 S.C.R. 330, para. 61).

 

        “Assessing credibility is not a science. It is very difficult for a trial judge to articulate with precision the complex intermingling of impressions that emerge after watching and listening to witnesses and attempting to reconcile the various versions of events…” (Gagnon, para. 20).

                 

        The exercise of articulating the reasons “for believing a witness and disbelieving another in general or on a particular point…may not be purely intellectual and may involve factors that are difficult to verbalize…In short, assessing credibility is a difficult and delicate matter that does not always lend itself to precise and complete verbalization” (R. v. R.E.M., 2008 SCC 51, para. 49).

 

        A trial judge does not need to describe every consideration leading to a finding of credibility, or to the conclusion of guilt or innocence (R.E.M., at para. 56).

 

        “A trial judge is not required to comment specifically on every inconsistency during his or her analysis”. It is enough for the trial judge to consider the inconsistencies and determine if they “affected reliability in any substantial way” (R. v. Kishayinew2019 SKCA 127, at para. 76, Tholl, J.A. in dissent; upheld 2020 SCC 34, para. 1).

 

        A trial judge should address and explain how they have resolved major inconsistencies in the evidence of material witnesses (R. v. A.M., 2014 ONCA 769, para. 14)

[68]         In G.F., the Supreme Court of Canada has recently warned against the parsing of a trial judge’s reasons, particularly as they relate to the assessment of credibility. An appellant must be able to show actual error or, due to insufficient reasons, the frustration of appellate review. The appellate court “must be rigorous in its assessment, looking to the problematic reasons in the context of the record as a whole and determining whether or not the trial judge erred or appellate review was frustrated” (para. 79).

[69]         The Court in G.F. acknowledged the particular challenges faced by judges assessing credibility in sexual assault trials:

[81]  As Slatter [R. v. Slatter2020 SCC 36] demonstrates, a trial judge's findings of credibility deserve particular deference. While the law requires some articulation of the reasons for those findings, it also recognizes that in our system of justice the trial judge is the fact finder and has the benefit of the intangible impact of conducting the trial. Sometimes, credibility findings are made simpler by, for example, objective, independent evidence. Corroborative evidence can support the finding of a lack of voluntary consent, but it is of course not required, nor always available. Frequently, particularly in a sexual assault case where the crime is often committed in private, there is little additional evidence, and articulating reasons for findings of credibility can be more challenging. Mindful of the presumption of innocence and the Crown's burden to prove guilt beyond a reasonable doubt, a trial judge strives to explain why a complainant is found to be credible, or why the accused is found not to be credible, or why the evidence does not raise a reasonable doubt.

Un élément important dans l'appréciation de la crédibilité d'un témoin est de constater l'existence ou non de contradiction sur un enjeu important

R. v. C.H., 1999 CanLII 18939 (NL CA)

Lien vers la décision


[23]                       One important aspect to be considered in assessing credibility, is consistency or lack of it in statements made by the witness when addressing the matter in the witness box and on other occasions. It is critically important therefore that a trial judge deal with indicated inconsistencies when assessing credibility of an only, or a critical, witness testifying against an accused. As Galligan, J.A., observed in R. v. M.G. (1994), 1994 CanLII 8733 (ON CA), 73 O.A.C. 356; 93 C.C.C. (3d) 347 (C.A.) at p. 354-355 [C.C.C.]:

“Probably the most valuable means of assessing the credibility of a crucial witness is to examine the consistency between what the witness said in the witness-box and what the witness has said on other occasions, whether on oath or not. Inconsistencies on minor matters or matters of detail are normal and are to be expected. They do not generally affect the credibility of the witness. This is particularly true in cases of young persons. But where the inconsistency involves a material matter about which an honest witness is unlikely to be mistaken, the inconsistency can demonstrate a carelessness with the truth. The trier of fact is then placed in the dilemma of trying to decide whether or not it can rely upon the testimony of a witness who has demonstrated carelessness with the truth.

“The effect of inconsistencies upon the credibility of a crucial witness was recently described by Rowles, J.A., speaking for the British Columbia Court of Appeal in R. v. B. (R.W.) (1993), 40 W.A.C. 1 at pp. 9-10, 19 W.C.B.(2d) 260:

‘Where, as here, the case for the Crown is wholly dependent upon the testimony of the complainant, it is essential that the credibility and reliability of the complainant’s evidence be tested in the light of all of the other evidence presented.

‘In this case there were a number of inconsistencies in the complainant’s own evidence and a number of inconsistencies between the complainant’s evidence and the testimony of other witnesses. While it is true that minor inconsistencies may not diminish the credibility of a witness unduly, a series of inconsistencies may become quite significant and cause the trier of fact to have a reasonable doubt about the reliability of the witness’s evidence. There is no rule as to when, in the face of inconsistency, such doubt may arise but at the least the trier of fact should look to the totality of the inconsistencies in order to assess whether the witness’s evidence is reliable. This is particularly so when there is no supporting evidence on the central issue, which was the case here.’

“That statement was adopted by Finlayson, J.A., speaking for this court in R. v. S. (W.) (1994), 1994 CanLII 7208 (ON CA), 90 C.C.C.(3d) 242 at pp. 252-4; 29 C.R.(4th) 143; 18 O.R.(3d) 509 (C.A.).” (Emphasis added.)

[24]                       No authority need be cited to support the proposition that observing demeanour is a major tool in the kit of a trial judge when assessing the credibility of a witness. However, as important as it is, credibility of a complainant accepted on the basis of demeanour alone, is not a sufficient basis to convict an accused where the allegations are credibly denied or there is other contradictory evidence. Finlayson, J.A., in R. v. W.S. (1994), 1994 CanLII 7208 (ON CA), 70 O.A.C. 370; 90 C.C.C.(3d) 242 (C.A.), at page 250 [C.C.C.] said:

“It is evident from his reasons that the trial judge was impressed with the demeanour of the complainant in the witness-box and the fact that she was not shaken in cross-examination. I am not satisfied, however, that a positive finding of credibility on the part of the complainant is sufficient to support a conviction in a case of this nature where there is significant evidence which contradicts the complainant’s allegations. We all know from our personal experiences as trial lawyers and judges that honest witnesses, whether they are adults or children, may convince themselves that inaccurate versions of a given event are correct and they can be very persuasive. The issue, however, is not the sincerity of the witness but the reliability of the witness’ testimony. Demeanour alone should not suffice to found a conviction where there are significant inconsistencies and conflicting evidence on the record: see R. v. Norman (1993), 1993 CanLII 3387 (ON CA), 87 C.C.C.(3d) 153 at pp. 170-4; 26 C.R.(4th) 256; 16 O.R.(3d) 295 (Ont. C.A.), for a discussion on this subject.”

Ce que la Cour d'appel de l'Ontario considère comme étant le moyen le plus précieux d'apprécier la crédibilité d'un témoin

R. v. M.G., 1994 CanLII 8733 (ON CA)

Lien vers la décision


[27]           Probably the most valuable means of assessing the credibility of a crucial witness is to examine the consistency between what the witness said in the witness-box and what the witness has said on other occasions, whether on oath or not. Inconsistencies on minor matters or matters of detail are normal and are to be expected. They do not generally affect the credibility of the witness. This is particularly true in cases of young persons. But where the inconsistency involves a material matter about which an honest witness is unlikely to be mistaken, the inconsistency can demonstrate a carelessness with the truth. The trier of fact is then placed in the dilemma of trying to decide whether or not it can rely upon the testimony of a witness who has demonstrated carelessness with the truth.

Résumé exhaustif du droit relatif à l'appréciation de la crédibilité d'un témoin

R. v. W.G.L., 2020 NSSC 144

Lien vers la décision


[23]         Jurisprudence recognizes that there is a difference between credibility and reliability. In R. v. Morrissey (1995), 1995 CanLII 3498 (ON CA), 22 O.R. (3d) 514 (C.A.), Doherty J.A. wrote (at p. 526):

Testimonial evidence can raise veracity and accuracy concerns. The former relate to the witness's sincerity, that is, his or her willingness to speak the truth as the witness believes it to be. The latter concerns relate to the actual accuracy of the witness's testimony. The accuracy of a witness's testimony involves considerations of the witness's ability to accurately observe, recall and recount the events in issue. When one is concerned with a witness's veracity, one speaks of the witness's credibility. When one is concerned with the accuracy of a witness's testimony, one speaks of the reliability of that testimony. Obviously a witness whose evidence on a point is not credible cannot give reliable evidence on that point. The evidence of a credible, that is, honest witness, may, however, still be unreliable. …

[24]          In R. v. H.C.2009 ONCA 56, 244 O.A.C. 288, Watt J.A. described the difference between credibility and reliability (at para. 41):

Credibility and reliability are different. Credibility has to do with a witness's veracity, reliability with the accuracy of the witness's testimony. Accuracy engages consideration of the witness's ability to accurately

(i)observe;

 

(ii)recall; and

 

(iii)recount

 

events in issue. Any witness whose evidence on an issue is not credible cannot give reliable evidence on the same point. Credibility, on the other hand, is not a proxy for reliability: a credible witness may give unreliable evidence: R. v. Morrissey (R.J.) (1995), 1995 CanLII 3498 (ON CA)80 O.A.C. 161; 22 O.R. (3d) 514 (C.A.), at 526 [O.R.].

[29]        In considering credibility in the case at Bar, I have carefully considered and applied the relevant jurisprudence as well as Justice Paciocco’s observations, the underlying principles he references, suggested “propositions”, and his “credibility checklist”.

[30]        I will quote directly from the article rather than attempt to summarize it:

“What, then, are the underlying principles that drive W. (D.) reasoning? Framed as they apply in criminal trials where there is evidence inconsistent with guilt, they are:

 

(1)   Criminal trials cannot properly be resolved by deciding which conflicting version of events is preferred;

 

(2)   A criminal fact-finder that believes evidence that is inconsistent with the guilt of the accused cannot convict the accused;

 

(3)   Even if a criminal fact-finder does not entirely believe evidence inconsistent with guilt, if the fact-finder is left unsure whether that evidence is true there is a reasonable doubt and an acquittal must follow;

 

(4)   Even where the fact-finder entirely disbelieves evidence inconsistent with guilt, the mere rejection of that evidence does not prove guilt; and

 

(5)   Even where the fact-finder entirely disbelieves evidence inconsistent with guilt, the accused should not be convicted unless the evidence that is given credit proves the accused guilty beyond a reasonable doubt.

  …

 

(b) The Reach of the “W. (D.) Framework”

 

Despite popular belief, the W. (D.) framework is not confined to “he said/she said” cases, or to sexual offence cases where the accused person testifies, such as R. v. W. (D.). The facts of the case do not drive the framework. Instead, the underlying purpose of preventing conviction in the face of reasonable doubt does.

 

The link between the W. (D.) framework and the concept of reasonable doubt can best be demonstrated by considering a civil case, C. (R.) v. McDougall.17 There the civil defendant sought to rely on W. (D.)'s underlying principles. The Supreme Court of Canada held that they do not apply, and with good reason, to the standard of proof in a civil case, which is “the balance of probabilities.” Consequentially, balance of probability inquiries can legitimately devolve into credibility contests. In a civil lawsuit, for example, the plaintiff will win if it offers testimony addressing the components of the relevant cause of action, and that testimony is preferred to conflicting testimony offered by the defendant.

 

*37 For this reason, the W. (D.) framework does not apply in criminal cases where the Crown bears a “balance of probabilities” burden, such as in criminal forfeiture order applications under s. 16 of the Controlled Drugs and Substances Act, or in mental disorder fitness hearings.

Similarly, the W. (D.) framework does not apply where “reasonable grounds” standards are used, such as in firearms prohibition applications under Criminal Code s. 111, or during contested “peace bond” hearings either at common law18or under Criminal Code s. 810 and its associated provisions.

Simply put, if the standard of proof assigned to the Crown is not proof beyond a reasonable doubt, the W. (D.) framework does not apply. If the standard of proof is beyond a reasonable doubt, the W. (D.) framework may apply, depending upon the nature of the factual issues at stake.

 

In an informative extra-judicial paper Justice M. Code offered judges this advice on the nature of the factual issues that trigger the framework:

 

“[T]he W. (D.) instruction should be introduced into your reasons, and into the charge to the jury, when dealing with elements of the offences charged and the elements of any defences raised by the evidence, assuming there is conflicting evidence in relation to those elements, thus giving rise to issues of credibility.”19

 

When Justice Code used the term “credibility” he did what all jurists do when it comes to W. (D.). He spoke of “credibility” not in its narrow, technical sense, as relating solely to whether the witness was attempting to be honest or truthful.20 He used the term “credibility” more generically as including “reliability” concerns relating to the ability of an honest witness to provide accurate information.

 

Simply put, when references are made in the W. (D.) framework to “credibility,” they must be understood as including both the credibility and reliability of the evidence in question.

The case of R. v. L. (T.)21 is illustrative. There, witnesses offered descriptions of the suspect that were inconsistent with the accused being the perpetrator. The Crown did not contend that these witnesses were being dishonest when describing the suspect. Its position was that other evidence in the case showed the witnesses to have honestly been mistaken. Even though technically the contest was about reliability and not credibility, the Ontario Court of Appeal held that the W. (D) framework should nonetheless have been applied to determine whether this identification raised a reasonable doubt about the guilt of the accused.22 References to “credibility” in the W. (D.) framework include “reliability.”

 

*38 The meaning of the term “conflicting evidence” referred to by Justice Code also has to be understood. First, this phrase is not confined to situations where two witnesses offer competing accounts. Suppose, for example, that the Crown case on the issue of identity is entirely circumstantial, as it would be where DNA or fingerprints are relied upon to link the accused to the offence. If the accused testified and denied committing the crime, the W. (D.) framework would have to be applied, even though no Crown witness said that the accused did so.

 

By the same token, as Justice Code's formula makes clear, not all conflicting evidence triggers the need for the W. (D.) framework. In the language of Justice Blair in R. v. D. (B.), the W. (D.) framework applies not to “any single fact or item of evidence”, but rather to “vital” issues,23 what Justice Code describes as the “elements of the offence,” or the “elements of a defence.”

 

…. As the Supreme Court of Canada made clear in R. v. Morin,24 the standard of proof, “beyond a reasonable doubt,” does not apply to “individual pieces of evidence.” It applies to the overall “determination of ultimate issues.”25

 

As indicated, Justice Code captured this basic point by referring in his proposition to conflicting evidence relating to the “elements of the offences charged and the elements of any defences raised by the evidence.” This is helpful, since these are the things that the burden of proof “beyond a reasonable doubt” generally applies to during a criminal prosecution. The Crown must always prove the elements of the offence beyond a reasonable doubt, and where an ordinary defence--such as self-defence, necessity, duress, provocation, or mistake of fact-- is in issue, the Crown must disprove that defence beyond a reasonable doubt.

 

Not all defences operate this way, however. There are three “reverse onus defences” known to law--“mental disorder,”26“automatism,”27 and “extreme *39 intoxication.”28 As the name “reverse onus defences” suggests, when these defences are put in play the Crown need not disprove them beyond a reasonable doubt, as it ordinarily must when there is an air of reality in the evidence that a defence might apply. Instead, the burden is on the accused to establish “reverse onus defences” on the balance of probabilities, or the defence fails. The W. (D.) framework therefore has no application when deciding whether reverse onus defences have been made out. The suggestion that the W. (D.) framework applies to “any defence” that is in issue should therefore be approached with caution. The framework applies to most defences--“ordinary defences”--but not to “reverse onus defences.”

 

Speaking generally then, there will be “conflicting evidence” giving rise to the application of the W. (D.) framework where testimony is offered during the guilt phase of the trial that, if believed, can raise a reasonable doubt on a matter the Crown is required to prove beyond a reasonable doubt to secure a conviction. As indicated, the framework will apply where this is so, even if testimony from the accused is not the source of the evidence inconsistent with guilt.”

 

Next, are the propositions that Justice Paciocco puts forward:

 

Proposition 1: The W. (D.) framework applies in determining guilt during criminal trials where:

 

• there is evidence (whether from the testimony of the accused, or defence witnesses, or arising from the Crown case) that, if true, is capable of preventing the Crown from proving beyond a reasonable doubt, (1) an element of the offence, or (2) capable of preventing the Crown from disproving beyond a reasonable doubt an element of a defence that is in play (other than mental disorder, automatism or extreme intoxication);and

 

• that evidence must be evaluated for its credibility and/or reliability before it can be acted upon.

 

Proposition 2--A criminal trial is not a “credibility contest.” It is a trial to determine whether the Crown has proved the guilt of the accused on the specific charges alleged, beyond a reasonable doubt. It is therefore wrong to decide criminal cases where there is conflicting evidence about whether the accused is guilty, simply by deciding which version of events is preferred. The decisive question is whether, considering the evidence as a whole, the Crown has proved the guilt of the accused on the specific charges alleged, beyond a reasonable doubt.

 

Proposition 3--In deciding whether the Crown has proved the accused to be guilty beyond a reasonable doubt:

 

(a)   If you accept as accurate evidence that cannot co-exist with a finding that the accused is guilty, obviously you must acquit;

 

(b)   If you are left unsure whether evidence that cannot co-exist with a finding that the accused is guilty is accurate, then you have not rejected it entirely and you must acquit;

 

(c)   You should not treat mere disbelief of evidence that has been offered by the accused to show his innocence as proof of the guilt of the accused; and

 

(d)   Even where evidence inconsistent with the guilt of the accused is rejected in its entirety, the accused should not be convicted unless the evidence that is given credit proves the accused to be guilty beyond a reasonable doubt.

 

Proposition 4--In deciding whether the Crown has proved the accused to be guilty beyond a reasonable doubt the evidence must be considered as a whole. It is therefore possible to reject entirely evidence that is inconsistent with the guilt of the accused and convict solely because of the considered and reasoned acceptance beyond a reasonable doubt of evidence that the accused is guilty.

 

 Proposition 5--As a matter of best practices in a judge alone trial where there is conflicting evidence about guilt that has to be evaluated for its credibility:

 

(a)   it is prudent to make explicit reference to the W. (D.) principles when giving judgment;

 

(b)   trial judges may assess the evidence in the order that logically commends itself, so long as they do not arrive at an ultimate conclusion about the guilt of the accused before considering the evidence in its entirety, and so *73 long as it is clear that they are not simply comparing conflicting evidence to find the version they prefer; and

 

(c) trial judges should explain how and why they have resolved each of the W. (D.) rules by addressing each of the important, live credibility issues that arose in the case.

 

Proposition 6--The principles underlying the W. (D.) framework, expressed to fit the relevant context, must be respected whenever there is testimony before a court that is inconsistent with an effort by the Crown to discharge a burden it carries to prove a fact beyond a reasonable doubt, including in voluntariness voir dires, during sentencing hearings where aggravated factors relied upon by the Crown are contested, or where the Crown seeks to rely on a single item of evidence that, if accepted, would be determinative of guilt.”

 

[31]        This is also an opportune moment to reiterate that, according to Justice Paciocco:

“it is common for jurists to believe… that if the exculpatory evidence, viewed alone, cannot be rejected in its entirety because of its own inherent credibility problems, an acquittal must follow. This is a misconception, no doubt provoked by the sequential presentation of the W. (D.) rules--“first,” “second,” “third.” In fact, evidence favourable to the accused is not to be assessed in isolation from the conflicting evidence offered by the Crown.56 Even under W. (D.), the evidence in a criminal trial must be considered as a whole. As a result, it is permissible for a trial fact-finder to reject entirely the exculpatory evidence simply because of the imposing strength of the Crown case, even if no specific reasons can be articulated for why the accused's evidence is disbelieved.

 

The decision in R. v. D. (J.J.R.),57 once again a “he said/she said” case, is illustrative.58 There, the trial judge explicitly recognized that “there was nothing in the substance of the appellant's evidence or in the manner in which he gave his evidence that would cause the trial judge to disbelieve the evidence.”59 A *48 conviction was nonetheless upheld because the trial judge “rejected totally the appellant's denial because stacked beside [the complainant's] evidence and the evidence concerning the diary,60 the appellant's evidence, despite the absence of obvious flaws in it, did not leave the trial judge with a reasonable doubt.” Justice Doherty went on to comment:

 

An outright rejection of an accused's evidence based on a considered and reasoned acceptance beyond a reasonable doubt of the truth of the conflicting evidence is as much an explanation for the rejection of an accused's evidence as is a rejection based on a problem identified with the way the accused testified or the substance of the accused's evidence.”61 [17]

 

  …

 

In my view, it is important to allay the misconception that an acquittal must follow if the defence evidence, viewed in isolation, cannot be disbelieved beyond a reasonable doubt. It is equally important, however, to emphasize the need for a demonstrably “considered and reasoned” basis for accepting the inculpatory evidence beyond a reasonable doubt before conviction is appropriate in such cases. I would therefore recommend the following proposition:

 

Proposition 4--In deciding whether the Crown has proved the accused to be guilty beyond a reasonable doubt the evidence must be considered as a whole. It is therefore possible to reject entirely evidence that is inconsistent with the guilt of the accused solely because of the considered and reasoned acceptance beyond a reasonable doubt of evidence that the accused is guilty.

 

[My italicization added]